The American Journal of Bioethics, 11(7): 32–45, 2011Copyright c Taylor & Francis Group, LLCISSN: 1526-5161 print / 1536-0075 onlineDOI: 10.1080/15265161.2011.568577
Target Article Health and Social Justice (Ruger 2009a) developed the “health capability paradigm,” a conception of justice and health in domestic societies. This idea undergirds an
alternative framework of social cooperation called “shared health governance” (SHG). SHG puts forth a set of moral responsibilities, motivational aspirations, and
institutional arrangements, and apportions roles for implementation in striving for health justice. This article develops further the SHG framework and explains its
importance and implications for governing health domestically. Keywords: health governance, health ethics, social cooperation, self-interest, shared health governance Health and Social Justice (Ruger 2009a) advances a series of
approaches, but in both, narrow self-interest is a chief
goals for domestic societies. It envisions societies in which
motivation. Some have sought to merge the study of game
all people can realize central health capabilities—to avoid
theory with that of ethics. These efforts, however, have
premature death and escapable morbidity. While no society
focused primarily on formalizing social contract theory and
can guarantee good health, societies can, if they will, create
demonstrating the rationality of acting morally in accord
the conditions—effective institutions, social systems, and
with particular principles agreed upon through bargaining
practices—to support all members as they seek to achieve
or negotiation (Gauthier 1986). The underlying premise
here is still primarily narrow self-interest. Few applications
This article continues this journey by considering who
of economic game and social contract theories in health
is responsible for various aspects of these social objectives
and health care exist and focus on distributing societal
and how societies might make this vision a reality. Societies
responsibility and benefits for the wider common good
differ significantly in the way in which they make decisions
and individual good simultaneously. Also, a growing body
and take actions regarding health and health care. Some see
of research “eschews a narrow conception of rationality”
governments as primarily responsible, setting up central-
altogether (Levitt and List 2008, 909).
ized national health systems. Others emphasize personal
This article takes a broad view of health governance.
responsibility, relying heavily on the free market and indi-
To create conditions in which all have the ability to be
vidual choice, as in the United States and most developing
healthy, the shared health governance (SHG) model sets
countries. Scholarly discourse maps these trends, ranging
out allocations of responsibility, resources, and sovereignty
from collective to individual responsibility, but the focus
to national and state governments and institutions, non-
has tended to be more general than health care specific.
governmental organizations (NGOs), the private sector,
In health care particularly, efforts toward responsibility
communities, families, and individuals themselves. In
assessment and assignment tend to be ad hoc, judging the
this view of health governance, ethical commitments are
ethical behavior of individuals and particular institutions
fundamental, in conjunction with institutions and policies.
like managed care organizations, for-profit hospitals, or the
SHG focuses on the alignment between the common good
medical profession (Wikler 2002; Buchanan 2009). This nar-
and self-interest: It seeks societal conditions to achieve
row approach diverts attention from the harder problem,
common and individual goods concurrently.
mapping the interdependent and shifting roles of different
Shared health governance is a more normatively appeal-
actors in fostering health at both individual and societal
ing and effective approach to governing health domestically
levels. Individual and population health require shared re-
as compared to existing alternatives. It asserts that as a so-
sponsibility, individual and collective. Social cooperation is
ciety we’re all responsible for doing our fair share to seek
health justice. Because health production at the individual
Economic cooperation theory offers both noncoop-
and population levels demands resources and public envi-
erative game theory and more cooperative game theory
ronments that are beyond any one individual’s or group’s
The author thanks the Patrick and Catherine Weldon Donaghue Medical Research Foundation, the Greenwall Foundation and the Yale
Center for Faith and Culture, and the McDonald Agape Foundation for financial support, and Jarrad Aguirre, Christina Lazar, Nora Ng,and Betsy Rogers for research and editing assistance. Thanks also go to participants at the Greenwall Faculty Scholars bi-annual meeting,the American Society for Bioethics and Humanities (ASBH) Annual Conference, the Workshop on Desire and The Common Good atYale Divinity School, and Wendy Farley, Jennifer Herdt, John Hare, David Kelsey, Alonzo McDonald, Russell Reno, Theodore Ruger, andMiroslav Volf for helpful comments. Address correspondence to Jennifer Prah Ruger, Yale University, 60 College Street, PO Box 208034, New Haven, CT 06520, USA. E-mail:jennifer.ruger@yale.edu
32 ajob
Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1752295
ability to provide, it necessitates shared resources that are
There are contrasts between NCGT and a cooperation
distributed fairly and efficiently. Because generating and
model such as SHG. For one, NCGT says little about val-
distributing resources fairly and efficiently require the at-
ues (except maximizing one’s own utility). Second, in NCGT
tention of us all—individuals, groups and institutions—we
each player makes her own decision, so there is no mutuality
are all responsible for steering such efforts. While the gov-
or shared deliberation. Third, classic NCGT games involve
ernment may assume the role of redistribution, regulation,
two players, so coalition building and group inclusion are
and oversight, we all must govern ourselves to ensure wise
absent, although group games have similar results (Bowles
and Gintis 2008). Fourth, under certain circumstances peo-
Health and health care decision making calls for in-
ple have an incentive to cheat or defect from cooperation in
put from both experts (e.g., medical professionals) and
one-time interactions or in instances when they can elude
laypersons (e.g., patients). Thus SHG involves shared
punishment, potentially leading to “a sequence of succes-
sovereignty—inclusive decision making and shared author-
sively higher order punishments” (Fudenberg and Maskin
ity. But the corollary to this privilege is the obligation to
make wise health decisions and take prudent health actions
A second class of economic cooperation theories is co-
operative game theory (CGT), which also presumes self-
Mutual collective accountability is the coin of the realm
interested rationality. CGT can describe either cooperative
in the SHG framework. Thus, consensus and congruence on
or competitive environments. CGT concentrates on possibil-
values and goals are important among government, health
ities for agreement, as well as on outcomes resulting from
providers, groups, and individuals, as is a shared under-
player cooperation in different combinations. By contrast
with NCGT, CGT places greater emphasis on coalition for-
Finally, SHG recognizes that while regulations and laws
mation and on promising and threatening behavior (Au-
are of great consequence to social cooperation, alone they
mann 2008). Common characteristics of CGT situations are
are not enough; although monitoring is important, no gov-
participants who can achieve benefits (such as power or
ernment agency can micromanage and police everyone in
money) from cooperation but who are in conflict over the
every situation. Thus, SHG relies on a specific type of social
division of benefits since each desires the greatest share for
norm—a public moral norm—and its correlative social sanc-
herself (Lemaire 1984). Participants (all or as subgroups) ne-
tions as a motivation and authoritative standard for action.
gotiate, bargain, and form coalitions in pursuit of gains, and
Internalized public moral norms convey society’s shared
will not accept less benefit than what can be attained alone.
values and goals and are important to making shared health
The division of group benefits ultimately depends upon the
relative power of participants. Players perceived as weak orof little value to the coalition may receive few if any benefitsin the final allocation scheme (Lemaire 1984; Arce M. andSandler 2003). THEORIES OF COOPERATION
Unlike SHG, the bargaining and division of benefits un-
An alternative model of social cooperation must situate it-
der CGT are based at least in part on “layers” of power and
self within the contours of existing work in cooperation
marginal contribution, which means that CGT is unlikely to
theory. Although an exhaustive review of the literature is
meet SHG’s goals of shared sovereignty or shared resources.
beyond this article’s scope, most economic theories of co-
For example, the distribution of gains from cooperation un-
operation, whether noncooperative or cooperative, rest on
der CGT could exclude weak, vulnerable, or marginalized
the premise of Homo economicus, that cooperation or lack
groups. Unlike SHG, CGT places little or no emphasis on
thereof involves strategic interactions among self-interested
public moral norms; a CGT bargain holds if it serves the
and rational individuals (e.g., individual utility or payoff
parties’ self-interest, not if it achieves an overarching social
objective. Finally, in the CGT model there is conflict among
Economic noncooperative game theory (NCGT) is un-
players over the division of benefits, reflecting a lack of con-
appealing for social cooperation in health even though
gruence on values and goals (except the goal of maximizing
it does not preclude cooperation. In NCGT, each player
one’s own utility or gains). SHG is more closely aligned
makes unilateral decisions driven by self-interest; coopera-
with cooperation models including other-regarding prefer-
tion must be self-enforcing—achieved and maintained only
ences and social norms (Ullmann-Margalit 1977) leading to
if each player cannot do better on her or his own. The Pris-
cooperation (Bowles and Gintis 2008). Moreover, additional
oner’s Dilemma (PD) is a classic example. In the one-shot PD
work on cooperation theory and empirical social science re-
game, each player maximizes her own payoff according to
search, particularly evolutionary game theory and biology
the PD payoff matrix without regard to the other player, and
and behavioral economics (Levitt and List 2008), provides
defection becomes the dominant strategy for each player
empirical evidence of the role of morality in solving recur-
even though cooperation between players would yield a
ring social problems, consistent with SHG.
better final outcome. In indefinitely iterated PD games, us-
A third general category of cooperation theory stems
ing a “tit-for-tat” strategy, players are able to punish each
from the social contract theory tradition. Social contractari-
other for defection in previous rounds, reputation matters,
anism is a major model and relates to CGT and bargaining
and there is a tendency toward cooperation.
theory. However, it assumes a “fundamental connection
ajob 33
Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1752295
between rationality and morality”—“moral norms . . . are
ers who have their own interests to pursue” (Ashford and
rationally acceptable . . . if . . . there is no feasible alternative
arrangement where all parties concerned would be better
Models of contractualism vary. Kantian forms seek prin-
off” (Verbeek and Morris 2010). Under social contractarian-
ciples expressing freedom and equality to which every agent
ism, individuals are mainly self-interested; they don’t neces-
would rationally agree (Rawls 1971). Though Rawls’s form
sarily have regard for others’ well-being. A reasoned pursuit
also seeks principles to which everyone would agree, the fo-
of self-interest leads to moral behavior, and moral norms are
cus is on political principles, not necessarily moral ones, and
based on maximizing interests jointly. Social contractarian-
principles of justice are chosen by self-interested agents act-
ism theories presume that the initial bargaining position is
ing behind a veil of ignorance (Rawls 1971). Thomas Scan-
characterized by scarcity or other cause for competition, and
lon’s version of contractualism bases morality on mutual
that social interaction and cooperation can produce gains
respect and looks for principles that “no one can reason-
(Cudd 2008). Social contractarianism also includes an ele-
ably reject” (as opposed to those on which everyone would
ment of power, since parties to a contract must have the
agree) under free and voluntary conditions (Scanlon 1998).
capacity to contribute to the product of social interaction
Scanlon does not propose a veil of ignorance; instead, in-
or at the very least pose a threat to it (Hartley 2009). In this
dividuals account for the interest of others through their
sense, social contractarianism is similar to CGT and exhibits
own desire to justify themselves to everyone else. Scanlon
the same differences from an SHG model in potentially leav-
places a more stringent criterion on how we live with oth-
ing certain groups—the severely disabled and other weak
ers: The fact that a principle negatively affects oneself is
and vulnerable groups—outside the realm of justice. The
insufficient reason for rejecting it. Individuals must rather
contract requires a “rationally acceptable” and “impartial”
ask how that principle affects others. In an interesting twist
starting point and procedures (e.g., no coercion or decep-
on the Pareto principle, Scanlon argues that the true test in
tion) to secure social cooperation (Gauthier 1986). Under so-
assessing moral principles from the agent’s point of view is
cial contractarianism, then, justice is possible where all those
not whether a principle imposes a burden on the agent, but
who are able to contribute benefit from the social contract.
whether the alternatives would place a heavier burden on
In Morals by Agreement, David Gauthier discusses “con-
others; if so, the agent cannot reasonably reject the principle
strained maximization,” in which players may actually do
(Scanlon 1998). Under this view, both self-interest and re-
better in many situations by eschewing “straightforward”
spect for others motivate actors, who owe it to one another
maximization and do not maximize self-interest (utility) at
to promote each other’s interests (Scanlon 1998). Thomas
every decision point, given the expectation of cooperation
Nagel, among others, has criticized Scanlon’s idea of prin-
from others (Gauthier 1986). Rationality can encompass in-
ciples no one can reasonably reject as impracticable, given
dividual decisions deemed suboptimal at the point of action.
the conflict of values in pluralist societies (Nagel 1991).
Moral constraint on pursuing self-interest is necessary be-
Contractualism actually shares some SHG elements.
cause individuals can almost always do better by cheating
Like SHG, it requires individuals and groups to consider
in cooperative activities while others keep to the bargain
others in their moral calculations, and demands that persons
promote others’ interests. Scanlon’s contractualism, in par-
Because social contractarianism shares many features
ticular, rejects self-interest maximization with an emphasis
with CGT, its contrasts with SHG are similar. Gauthier’s
on narrow individual rational agency. By focusing primarily
version, however, does introduce an element of normative
on individuals as they relate to each other, however, contrac-
constraint on “straightforward” self-interest maximization
tualism, unlike SHG, does not provide adequate scope for
that may be conducive to larger social interests. Moreover,
aggregate or societal concerns. Moreover, unlike contractu-
the element of conditioning oneself to restrain self-interest
alism, SHG recognizes that there may be some actions that
for the sake of keeping an agreement is appealing, although,
do impose greater burdens on others (e.g., requiring others
like SHG’s public moral norm internalization, likely difficult
to pay more for health insurance so the agent at hand has
coverage) that are still justified as long as the sacrifice of
Social contractualism is another idea stemming from
others does not interfere with their own ability to ensure
this tradition. Under contractualism, the rationality condi-
central health capabilities. Nor does it offer a sufficiently
tion takes a slightly different twist: We must respect per-
comprehensive approach to encompass shared sovereignty,
sons, which entails that moral principles be justifiable to
shared responsibility, and shared resources.
each person. Individuals are thus motivated by a commit-
A final category of social cooperation to assess in
ment to being able to justify their actions to others, rather
conjunction with SHG is utilitarianism. While there are
than by self-interest (Scanlon 1998). The principle of persons
many varieties of utilitarianism, some main features in-
having equal moral status grounds social contractualism.
clude grounding individuals’ moral status in happiness,
Moral behavior results from agreements that bind free and
desire fulfillment, and well-being, allowing interpersonal
equal moral agents. Comparing social contractarianism and
comparisons and aggregation of welfare and burdens, and
contractualism, the former describes a society in which in-
an overall social goal of maximizing utility for all (aggregate
dividuals aim to maximize self-interest in bargaining or ne-
utility), or in “average utilitarianism,” a goal of the highest
gotiating with others, whereas under contractualism, each
average level of utility (e.g., Bentham 1961). Utilitarianism
individual pursues her interest by means justifiable to “oth-
demands impartiality such that everyone’s utility is counted
34 ajob
equally in the aggregation scheme, although some have in-
that caused 500 deaths. It paid civil penalties to avoid crim-
troduced equity weights to modify this requirement (e.g.,
inal charges, but then lobbied to ban future lawsuits against
manufacturers of such devices (Palast 2002). Another com-
Utilitarianism contrasts with SHG in this particular
pany introduced a heart device (Prizm 2 DR) that malfunc-
impartiality requirement because the SHG framework in-
tioned in more than 33% of patients over a 19-month period,
volves special efforts to include weak and vulnerable
and failed to report to the U.S. Federal Drug Administration
groups; utilitarianism does not give these groups special
(FDA) the resulting 57 emergency surgeries and 12 deaths
consideration. Moreover, the goal of maximizing overall
utility does not address the distribution of utility. “Aver-
The FDA itself is not immune to these concerns. Many
age utilitarianism” might mitigate this concern, but does
assert that its funding structure renders it vulnerable to con-
not really solve the problem of addressing those with the
flict of interest. Half of the FDA’s budget for reviewing mar-
greatest needs. Utilitarianism, unlike SHG, lacks emphasis
keting applications comes from the drug industry (Willman
on individual agency or autonomy; collective interest may
2000). Ten of 32 members of the FDA advisory committee
override individual interest. But utilitarianism does require
deliberating Vioxx and Bextra withdrawal had conflicts of
actors to consider the impact of actions on others, because
interest with drug companies (Harris and Berenson 2005).
the goal is to maximize overall utility. Maximization of indi-
Of the 13 drugs removed from the market since 1997, at least
vidual self-interest cannot be the coin of the realm; trade-offs
7 had been approved despite the objections of FDA safety
among individuals are required, as in SHG.
Even the research and academic community faces con-
cerns about integrity of research and reporting due to in-
SELF-INTEREST MAXIMIZATION AND SUBOPTIMAL
dustry ties. For example, a 2000 New England Journal ofOUTCOMES IN HEALTH AND HEALTH CARE Medicine article omitted some risks of Vioxx; all 13 authors
Self-interest (e.g., individual utility or payoff) maximization
were connected with the Vioxx maker Merck, through em-
is at the heart of most theories of cooperation. From the per-
ployment or other financial relationships (Bombardier et al.
spective of social cooperation in health and health care, nar-
2000). Suppression of damaging results also occurred in the
row self-interest maximization alone produces suboptimal
case of the drug Synthroid (Rennie 1997) and a drug for
results. In U.S. health care, there are examples of medical
thalassemia major (Baird et al. 2002).
providers (doctors), drug and medical device businesses, in-
Both providers and patients commit Medicaid and
surance companies, and patients maximizing their own in-
Medicare fraud. Providers bill for services not ren-
terests without internalizing system-wide effects. Geyman
dered, double-bill to both Medicaid/Medicare and to pa-
(2008) compiled an extensive collection of examples from
tients/private insurance, upcode, and use unauthorized
the United States. Some doctors receive kickbacks from re-
service suppliers but bill at authorized supplier rates,
ferrals, refer patients to medical facilities in which they have
among other tactics. Patients loan Medicaid/Medicare ID
financial stakes, recommend and perform unnecessary pro-
cards to others, deliberately receive duplicate or excessive
cedures, and collect payments and gifts from hospitals and
services and/or supplies, and sell Medicaid/Medicare sup-
medical suppliers. In-depth studies of high-cost communi-
ties confirm many of these trends (Gawande 2009). Even
Such corrosive behaviors are not unique to the Ameri-
doctors’ choice of specialties is affected by material con-
can health care system. Health worker absenteeism, nepo-
cerns, as they avoid lower paying but crucial fields like fam-
tistic hiring, medical supply theft, and corrupt procure-
ily medicine, internal medicine, and pediatrics. Only about
ment are significant problems in countries such as Uganda,
10% of American medical students choose one of these fields
Bosnia, Dominican Republic, Argentina, and Venezuela, just
for residency training (Pugno et al. 2005); meanwhile, 70%
to name a few (Lewis 2006). Staffing shortages are some-
of the doctors in the United Kingdom and 50% in Canada
times further exacerbated by professional turf protection,
are in primary care (Starfield 1994). A weak primary care
where higher level professionals resist delegation of tasks
base renders the U.S. system excessively specialized and
to lower ones. One example is Botswanan doctors resisting
blood drawing by phlebotomists even in the face of staff
Many for-profit entities boost profits by various means.
shortage, thus hindering the scale-up of antiretroviral ther-
For example, one for-profit hospital chain was found to
apy (Swidler 2006). There are a number of structural factors
have inflated operating room charges by more than 800%
contributing to these practices and they undermine health
and collected fees more than 17 times that of public hospi-
efforts and waste scarce public health resources.
tals for blood tests (Benda 2003; Lagnado 2004). Diagnostic,
The starkness of these examples does not necessar-
screening, and imaging centers often have arrangements in
ily represent universal behavior but serves to highlight
which they charge discounted prices to doctors (e.g., $400
the underlying importance of working within a frame-
per scan, $850 per MRI), while doctors receive $2,300 from
work of shared and individual goals simultaneously. The
insurers for each MRI (Armstrong 2005). Such practices lead
idea is not to deny or eliminate altogether self-interest
to overuse of needless services. Medical suppliers have been
as a human motivation; rather, it is to recognize it, align
known to market and sell defective or unapproved medical
with shared goals, and create conditions (including insti-
devices. One supplier made and sold defective heart valves
tutions and policies that structure incentives) to reduce its
ajob 35
negative, and enhance its positive, impact on health care and
tween policymaking and scientific advice is questionable
(Fischer 2008). SHG maintains a middle view that recog-nizes the essential roles both of proceduralism for publicengagement and of epistemic values and standards for eval-
MODELS OF GOVERNANCE
uating deliberative outcomes. While beyond this article’s
The most widely employed approach to rein in self-interest
scope to explore at greater length, SHG engages with el-
maximization in any field, including health and health care,
ements of “epistemic proceduralism” (Estlund 2008) in its
is government regulation, although strong government is
only one type of governance. This section contrasts SHG
Decentralized, civic participation models of governance
with different models of governance.
include quite a few variants. For example, another EU food
There are at least two major types of governance mod-
safety regulation model is “reflexive” governance, which
els: top-down, hierarchical models, and decentralized/civic
acknowledges that “facts are uncertain, values in dispute,
participation models. Top-down, centralized, hierarchical
stakes high and decisions urgent” (Fischer 2008, quoting
governance is state-directed health system control, with
Funtowicz and Ravetz 1993, 739). It seeks permanent, open
the former Soviet Union (USSR) being a prominent and
lines of communication among experts, politicians, and the
extreme example. The USSR federal Health Ministry in
public, and attempts to “democratize” science by “con-
Moscow controlled medical education and training, health
trol[ling] scientists in expert committees” and presenting
care facilities, personnel, and finances throughout the USSR,
the views of laypersons (Fischer 2008, 6). This is contrary to
setting total health expenditures and allocating resources
the central role SHG gives to science; it also reflects an overly
through annual and five-year plans. Regional and local
optimistic view of civil society, NGOs, and laypersons as
health authorities operated under ministry budgets and
key decision makers, ignoring the potential for laypersons
rules, with little flexibility to address local needs (Row-
to add inefficiency, irrationality, and incoherence to health
land and Telyukov 1991). Another version of this top-down,
policy decision making (Fischer 2008). The classic interest-
government-mandated governance is the New Manageri-
group representation model is a version of civic participa-
alist/New Public Management model. “Process-oriented”
tion, but one that underscores some undesirable features
and “target-driven,” this model aims to reduce health ser-
in a governance model: interest-group competition in rule-
vice inefficiencies, close gaps, and reduce overlaps in ser-
making; rulemaking based on log-rolling between agency
vices, with the goal of moving individuals “to cheaper
and stakeholders; the treatment of agency officials as in-
parts” of the system (Rummery 2009, 1802). Both the cen-
siders and other stakeholders as outsiders; adversarial re-
tralized Soviet model and New Managerialism reflect the
lationships among stakeholders; and government serving
ideologies and goals of the center rather than local need. To
primarily as a “neutral and reactive arbiter among stake-
different degrees, the top-down hierarchical nature of both
models is contrary to SHG. Where the center dictates poli-
New localism and “local state entrepreneurialism” are
cies and procedures, there is little mutual collective account-
additional examples of models that place heavy empha-
ability, little involvement of individuals and the commu-
sis on civic participation. Citizens are asked to get involved
nity, and little effort to achieve the consensus or agreement
in “every government directive” (Blakeley 2006, 139). These
sought by SHG and contractualist approaches. Resources
approaches may not empower citizens as much as expected.
are shared, but often in arbitrary and unproductive ways.
Constant citizen consultation can result in fatigue and dis-
Two other examples of hierarchical governance models
engagement. Citizens are pressed to work with govern-
have been examined within the context of evolving Euro-
ment and the private sector, while entrenched inequalities in
pean Union (EU) food safety regulation (Fischer 2008). One
power and influence are not addressed; “professionalizing”
is technocratic governance, where technical experts dom-
citizen participation means that not all citizens are neces-
inate and make decisions. Politicians (nonexperts) rubber-
sarily equally empowered. Participation as a governmental
stamp those policies since they lack the knowledge and abil-
scheme may be a means of co-opting important citizens
ity to understand complicated scientific and technological
and “legitimizing domination,” instead of a strategy of em-
issues. Public participation is unnecessary in the “produc-
powerment (Blakeley 2006, 140). While new localism shares
tion of scientific expertise” (Fischer 2008, 5). “Decisionist”
SHG’s focus on individual agency, SHG relies significantly
governance takes the opposite approach, giving priority to
more on the give and take between the established social
political decision makers over scientific experts in the in-
order and individuals, and on an overarching framework
terest of clear accountability. Both these hierarchical models
of consensus on societal health goals. Moreover, in SHG,
also run counter to SHG. While SHG respects scientific infor-
participation and consensus seek to recognize inequalities
mation and expertise, it differs from the technocratic model
in understanding that political legitimacy involves norma-
Additional variants of decentralized, civic participation
tive reasoning and public deliberation. Political decisions
governance models exist that still differ from SHG but share
are not purely scientific (Gutmann and Thompson 2002).
some important elements. Co-governance combines “a
And even scientific experts can disagree (Fischer 2008). The
strong state, extensive market economies, and a lively civil
decisionist approach recognizes the political nature of pol-
society” (Roiseland 2010, 140). Local governments share
icy decisions, but the effectiveness of strict separation be-
power and govern with actors like local businesses, civil
36 ajob
organizations, and neighboring cities, steering such efforts
licanism emphasizes citizen deliberation and a pursuit of
through “network management” or “metagovernance”
(Roiseland 2010, 141). Like SHG, co-governance calls
Finally, another decentralized model of governance is
for collaboration among public, private, and civil actors
the Boundary-Spanning Policy Regime (B-SPR), for unruly
within the public sector or within levels of government.
cross-sector problems primarily at the domestic national
However, co-governance lacks SHG’s emphasis on social
level (Jochim and May 2010). B-SPRs bridge multiple pol-
norms, which helps hold cooperation together. Under
icy domains and encourage “integrative policies” by “pres-
co-governance, cooperation would be hard to maintain
sur[ing]” actors in relevant domains to work “more or less
in difficult situations, as actors may cease cooperation if
in accord toward similar ends” (Jochim and May 2010, 307).
further collaboration produces no common gains. Account-
The goal is to achieve greater policy cohesion and to make
ability mechanisms are also weakened by the removal of
up for governance fragmentation. Examples of B-SPRs in
decisions from elected institutions (Roiseland 2010).
the literature include community empowerment and pol-
Community governance and collaborative governance
lution abatement in the 1960s and 1970s; in the 1980s and
models both devolve governance to lower tiers of gov-
1990s, drug criminalization, disability rights, and welfare
ernment, frequently the local and even institutional level.
responsibility; and in the 2000s, homeland security.
Under community governance, community representatives
Civic republicanism, community and collaborative gov-
influence and specify policy, especially social welfare pol-
ernance, and B-SPRs have features in common with SHG,
icy, to best serve local needs and to build capacity through
but SHG places greater emphasis on meta-rules within a
youth and community consultation, local adaptation of ex-
higher level structure assigning responsibility and stipu-
ternally specified services, and greater awareness of re-
lating authority for public and private actors in the joint
source use (O’Toole et al. 2010). Collaborative governance
collaboration in health, as discussed next.
emphasizes “problem-solving . . . information-sharing anddeliberation among knowledgeable parties,” the “partici-pation of interested and affected parties in all stages of
SHARED HEALTH GOVERNANCE
the decision-making process,” and the “development of
The academic and policy work in social cooperation and
temporary rules subject to revisions” based on “continu-
governance helps illuminate efforts to organize collectively
ous monitoring and evaluation” (Zabawa 2003, 378). Ex-
in health and health care. But despite progress in institu-
amples of applications of collaborative governance include
tional design, many efforts have begun with a problematic
the public–private partnerships to expand health coverage
orientation in health and health care: To found a theory of
under the U.S. Health Insurance Flexibility and Account-
cooperation and governance on the “singular subject” the-
ability (HIFA) waiver, Seattle’s neighborhood planning pro-
ory of rational individualistic thinkers and actors. Entities,
gram, and the U.S. Environmental Protection Agency (EPA)
individuals or groups, are seen as isolated agents, even if
projects on watershed, Superfund, and environmental jus-
they act collectively. On the other hand, a focus solely on the
tice issues (Zabawa 2003; Neshkova 2010). Like SHG, col-
common good, overriding individual interests, is equally
laborative governance emphasizes actors’ interdependence
unsatisfactory. What’s required is the preservation of the
and accountability, with the government or a designated
methodological and normative importance of individuals,
agency at the center. SHG, however, sees government as
adding to it that of collectives as a whole.
more than simply a “facilitator of multi-stakeholder nego-
A narrow lens cannot accommodate continual interac-
tiations” (Zabawa 2003, 378). It allocates more authority
tions of individuals and groups in a cascade of iterative
to government in the framework for mutual collective ac-
and cumulative processes. Even the most basic health care
countability, to enhance the legitimacy of both government
example—the doctor–patient relationship—demonstrates
and nongovernment actors. SHG also calls for a reorien-
the extensive “jointness” and “interaction” involved in
tation of underlying norms and motivations for authentic
health and health care. Producing an effective and efficient
health system, and ultimately individual and population
The civic republican ideal envisions citizens connected
health, requires shared resources, shared sovereignty, and
in pursuit of the greater common good. One view of civic
shared responsibility based on the specific functions and
republicanism directs lawyers, for example, to identify the
roles individuals and groups take on in this enterprise. Thus,
common good and to align their clients’ endeavors with so-
rather than relying solely on individualistic rationality, SHG
cial justice; thus, oddly, within this tradition lawyers don’t
concentrates additionally on social rationality in an alterna-
pursue only their clients’ interests. Preferences develop “di-
tive view of health governance, which seeks to help us better
alogically, through a process of engagement and discussion
understand how to effectuate principles of health and social
among citizens” (Wendel 2001, 2000). Other versions of civic
republicanism permit lawyers, as representatives of their
The first basic premise of the SHG framework is a
clients, to pursue client interests, but stipulate that lawyers
social scientific one: Multiple societal actors, public and
work toward the greater good of the system on their own
private, engage in a joint enterprise that either by omission
time (Gordon 1988). Deliberation does not merely present
fails or by collective action succeeds in co-producing
extant preferences; participants must be ready to amend
the conditions (including institutions and policies that
their preferences according to the public good. Civic repub-
structure incentives) for all to be healthy. SHG offers an
ajob 37
alternative set of fundamental assumptions for collective
mechanisms and places both individual health agency and
social norms (particularly public moral norms) as central
The second basic premise is both normative and social
to its framework. SHG recognizes that not only is it im-
scientific: Approximating justice in health requires individ-
possible to micromanage all actors’ health and health care
ual and group commitments to produce this social goal. A
behavior at all times, but such micromanagement may be
specific type of social norm—public moral norm—is put
less effective than social norm internalization. Internalized
forth as an effective motivation and authoritative standard
norms provide a shared authoritative standard by which
for individual and group action on health justice. Internal-
individuals and groups can use their health agency to make
ized public moral norms convey the shared values and goals
more effective decisions for optimal individual and societal
of society and are key for SHG’s successful realization. The
framework needs to work out issues related to this premise:
A sixth premise involves shared sovereignty and con-
Who frames the norms, situations of disagreement with the
norms, requirements for adhering to them, and better un-
The extensive theorizing and empiricism about
derstanding of how norms are internalized and followed
governance and the oscillation between ends of the
and what proportion of people need follow them. Lessons
central–local, expert–layperson, scientific–political, and
from public health (e.g., vaccination) and environmental
procedural–substantive spectra demonstrate how frustrat-
policy (e.g., recycling) are instructive here.
ingly difficult it is to fine-tune institutional designs to get at
A third basic premise stresses that generating a shared
improved health governance. And regardless of the inten-
commitment to an ideal or set of ideals can serve as the stim-
tion to rein it in, self-interest maximization can take hold
ulus for attention and role fulfillment across governance
and produce suboptimal results in virtually every gover-
subsystems (e.g., financing, organization, delivery of health
nance model. These models fall short of instilling a holistic
care). The ideas constitutive of the shared commitment bind
sense of what is to be shared and mutual: (i) actions and
the subsystems together to achieve a common purpose. Il-
goals, (ii) responsibility, (iii) resources, (iv) norms, and (v)
lustrations of such ideas are found in the principles and
sovereignty. An internalized and joint ethical commitment
their application as put forth in Health and Social Justice.
to ensure the conditions for all to be healthy undergirds
This shared commitment can in turn lead to political obli-
SHG and serves as motivation to hold ourselves account-
gations and commitments. The actors then give legitimacy
able for our respective roles and conduct. SHG does not
and power to that regime, forming the bases of support for
deny or seek to eliminate altogether self-interest or individ-
SHG. No single decision accomplishes this, but simultane-
ual “rationality”; rather, it aims to align it with shared goals
ous decisions together bring the SHG framework to fruition.
through joint commitments. By jointly committing to this
A fourth basic SHG premise is shared resources. Part
enterprise we accept our shared responsibility for health.
of the social commitment to ensuring the conditions forall individuals to be healthy involves sharing individual
GENERAL AND SPECIFIC DUTIES AT THE NATIONAL
and social resources. There are three components to thispremise. The first is the commitment to contribute one’s
LEVEL: A RECAP OF HEALTH AND SOCIAL JUSTICE
fair share to the collective pot to fund the joint enterprise. AND OTHER WORKS
The implementation of this principle involves progressive
Health and Social Justice argued for a universal duty to re-
financing such that, on a sliding scale, wealthier individuals
duce shortfall inequalities in central health capabilities as
and groups pay a greater percentage based on the overall
efficiently as possible and conceived of SHG as a gover-
level of wealth. The second is on the receiving end and
nance model for achieving this general obligation. All in-
is the conviction that each individual is entitled to receive
dividuals have obligations to each other, obligations dis-
that person’s fair share of resources. The implementation
charged through our own actions and through public and
of this principle allocates resources based, for example, on
private actors and institutions. Obligations of health jus-
the criteria of health functioning and health agency needs.
tice are grounded in individuals as members of a cooper-
The third is the responsibility to use these shared resources
ative joint venture to produce a health society. These du-
wisely and parsimoniously and not to demand more than
ties involve creating and upholding conditions for all to be
one’s fair share, based on bona fide needs as opposed to
healthy. SHG rests on a robust sense of shared responsibil-
desires or preferences. We all share in the benefits that ac-
ity. Thus, we need public moral norm internalization and
crue to society from achieving justice in health, including a
voluntary commitments to recognize and take ownership
more healthy, stable, well-cared-for, productive population,
in this cooperative enterprise, ownership that applies both
as well as cost containment and reduction in disease risk.
to our own actions and in holding institutions accountable.
Thus, we all share in mobilizing and using the resources
Political obligations follow from these duties.
In other works, this line of reasoning is taken a step
A fifth premise comprises enforcement and social sanc-
further, providing a theory for assigning responsibilities
tions created to hold actors responsible, apportioned sym-
among the multitudes of institutions and actors (Ruger
metrically according to the responsibilities attached to SHG
2009b). A theory of health justice necessitates additional
functions and roles. While SHG includes a role for incen-
principles for distributing responsibility to ground the
tives and external motivation, it does not rely solely on such
obligations of specific actors and institutions. Principles
38 ajob
identified for allocating specific duties involve (i) functional
barked on in Health and Social Justice to set out for society
and role-based requirements and (ii) voluntary commit-
as a public which moral ideas serve as guides and which
ments. Under the functional and role-based requirements
ought to be favored or disfavored. I agree, in part, with
principle, SHG dispenses functions and roles to those in-
Elizabeth Anderson in arguing that public moral norms au-
dividuals and groups best situated by their positions and
tonomously motivate our behavior and do not necessarily
require appeal to self-interest or even to the threat of social
The voluntary commitments principle asserts that indi-
sanctions (Anderson 2000). In many individual decisions
viduals and groups voluntarily embrace their role, share re-
about health and health care, it will not be possible or even
sources, and relinquish some autonomy through collective
desirable to apply social or even emotional sanctions for
action to address health problems. This links with a consen-
enforcement—on individuals failing to comply with AIDS
sus on a shared authoritative standard (discussed later) for
medication instructions, for example, or on doctors recom-
specific duties so that specific actors and institutions will
mending treatments to patients. Rather, we require a more
fulfill their obligations. In other words, specific actors and
profound commitment to both the individual (building on
institutions intend to be bound by these obligations, with
self-regard as a human motivation) and the common good,
a clear understanding of what they are to do. The process
an understanding that we work together as a body to create
of reaching consensus on specific duties in turn relates to
the conditions for all (including ourselves) to be healthy.
actors internalizing public moral norms, for example, pub-
The autonomy of the normative motivation under an
lic moral norms of health equity, motivating them to act
SHG framework is important. Willingly living out the pub-
to reduce inequalities in health capabilities as efficiently as
lic moral norm is important for achieving conditions for
possible. Efforts to establish consensus, through for exam-
individual and population health. It is significant if we are
ple incompletely theorized agreements, amidst pluralism,
to reach a steady state of enabling conditions. Millions of
individual decisions to get vaccinated for H1N1 or to ad-
Ethical commitments to this goal are key to motivating
here to tuberculosis treatment regimens or to cover one’s
actors, both in sacrificing resources and autonomy and in
mouth when one sneezes or wash one’s hands or to provide
discharging their duties. Voluntary commitments enhance
recommendations for high-quality, cost-effective care are
individual liberty by appealing to individually agreed-upon
illustrations. Internalized public moral norms also entail,
and embraced principles. The next section discusses public
like the Golden Rule, the recognition that we’re all hanging
moral norms as a shared authoritative standard for individ-
together in this enterprise: That we’re as likely to benefit
from a society where all can be healthy as to contribute toit. Thus, the public moral norm incorporates interest foroneself (self-interest) in the context of society as well as in-
PUBLIC MORAL NORMS AS A SHARED AUTHORITA-
terests for others. It links and aligns individual and society. TIVE STANDARD
While sanctions, incentives, and punishments can be helpful
The content of SHG’s social norms is an important focal
(e.g., in binding doctors to comply with standards for what
point. To unpack this idea, we differentiate between pub-
they recommend to patients or regulating what providers
lic and private norms. Public, here, means applicable to the
can discuss with patients), without the autonomous effect
public sphere. So a public norm is a form of social norm since
of internalized norms on individuals embracing their re-
it applies to the social sphere, as opposed to applying only
sponsibility for themselves and society, there will likely be
to our private spheres, but a public norm, in this view, has
insufficient motivation to act, and the wisdom and skills un-
more political heft, concerning what we do as a society, with
derpinning action will not develop over time. The claim is
public resources in publicly created conditions. While it de-
not that this type of norm is “all effective” but that it can as-
rives its content from the public and social, its internaliza-
sist in improving effectiveness. To achieve socially rational
tion and application involve both public and private actors.
objectives we need socially informed individual judgments
It is important to stress the morality of the norm. Norms
of behavior can, in fact, be immoral, such as infanticide,rape, pillage, and corruption. A moral norm, by contrast,involves a deep shared conviction of its “rightness” or at the
COMMITMENTS,
very least its lack of “wrongness.” An example is the fairness
RESPECTIVE ROLES
norm known as the Golden Rule, which some have argued
The third premise of SHG calls for a joint commitment
is engrained in human culture, having evolved with the hu-
among individuals and society to work together to secure
man species (Binmore 2005). SHG therefore employs public
the conditions for all to be healthy. Under this premise,
moral norms in creating a standard for joint commitments
individuals and groups will be committed to doing their
and joint decision making. Health and Social Justice, argued,
fair share, including playing allocated roles, in creating
however, that not all moral norms are equally desirable for
these conditions. This joint or societal commitment is a key
health and health care. There are even some moral norms
premise of the SHG framework. This feature shares the ele-
whose fairness is debatable, such as absolutist libertarian
ments of self-understanding and identity with frameworks
or individualist theoretical approaches as applied to health
of collective agency and group membership put forward in
and health care. The SHG project continues the journey em-
social theory (e.g., Tuomela 1984; Gilbert 1989; Searle 1990). ajob 39 The “We” in Health and Health Systems, A Nod to
stitute a fair share, nor what constitutes a reasonable defini-
Plural Subject Theory
tion of health justice, it can buttress the idea that individuals
This third premise of SHG is conducive to theorization un-
in a society have a political obligation to one another. This
der “plural subject” theory (PST) (Gilbert 1989). PST ex-
political obligation could involve supporting laws or norms
plores the self-understanding of individuals in a group who
that strive to foster, for example, health capabilities.
view themselves and one another as a body of people jointly
Another question is whether SHG could, at least tem-
porarily, rely on a political obligation to inculcate certain
In the PST account, joint commitments create an ex-
norms and align behaviors with them. But even if individu-
ternal force that binds one to act or believe a certain way,
als have a political obligation to do X, as theorized by PST,
counter to expected actions or beliefs absent the commit-
one must wonder how relevant this obligation is if individu-
ment. The joint commitment thus creates a binding rule, so
als do not believe it to be legitimate, and if it is not enforced.
to speak, that individuals follow even when the rule might
The SHG framework of internalizing norms and behaviors,
conflict with short-term rational self-interest. Individuals
while more time-intensive, seems a sustainable approach.
are answerable, to others and to themselves, for violations.
One key is the norm or set of norms emerging to be viewed
The plural subjects in SHG are all of us. As plural sub-
jects acting and in many cases working together, we create
DIVISION RESPONSIBILITY
(or by omission or action fail to create) the conditions forall individuals (including ourselves) to be healthy. The PST
RESPONSIBILITY
understanding that “social groups” are “plural subjects”
SHG entails individuals taking actions to improve their own
and that “plural subject phenomena” include “social rules
health, building on self-regard as a human motivation, as
and conventions, group languages, everyday agreements,
well as that of others, and encompasses duties to avoid
collective beliefs and values, and genuinely collective emo-
harming others and the system as a whole. SHG parts com-
tions” (Gilbert 2003, 55) is highly relevant to SHG. Among
pany with the pure notion of collective belief in the soci-
the features stipulated by PST for joint commitments and
ological sense (that a belief can inhere in the social group
plural subject-hood are: (i) open expression of willingness
without individuals in that group taking it on individually).
or “quasi-readiness” to do X together, where X connotes
Individual-level believing and thinking are a necessary part
a belief or action (Gilbert 1989; Gilbert 2003); (ii) common
of the SHG framework, fundamental to the principle of re-
knowledge among the plural subjects that others have ex-
sponsibility allocation and responsibility division. SHG in-
pressed willingness to do X together (this constitutes an
volves spontaneous convergence, since explicit agreements
element of trust in the reciprocity of others’ behavior and is
at every stage and every decision point are not possible.
akin to the sociological notion of “consciousness of unity”
Specific responsibilities in the collective arrangement fall to
(Schmitt 2003); and (iii) obligations binding plural members
those who, by their roles or resources, are best positioned
of the group together, such that “each party is answerable
to all parties for any violation of the joint commitment”
Based on these principles, the primary responsibility for
efficiently reducing shortfall inequalities in central health
Under SHG, individuals need to express “readiness”
capabilities should be allocated to the state (federal gov-
to endow an individual or a group of individuals with
ernment), because national governments have the political
decision-making power—forming a basic joint commitment
authority, resources, and regulatory and redistributive abili-
to embrace public moral norms, for example, of health eq-
ties to create health system infrastructures, including health
uity. Then individuals are politically obligated to uphold
care, public health, and other systems affecting health, like
these decisions; political obligations flow from such com-
food, drug, consumer, and work safety. They are also in the
mitments. SHG diverges a bit from PST, however, in the
best position to create and disseminate public goods neces-
content of the moral imperative. PST does not distinguish
sary for sustaining central health capabilities. National du-
between types of political obligations. Political obligations
ties include developing and maintaining a national health
related to health under PST, for example, might not entail
care and public health system that guarantees a universal
a significantly binding commitment as related to political
comprehensive benefits package of medically necessary and
obligations in other domains. However, under SHG, if po-
medically appropriate goods and services, and that creates
litical obligations related to health can be persuasively bol-
an environment that supports central health capabilities.
stered by moral considerations, they could entail a robust
National duties also involve delegating specific duties to
commitment as related to other types of commitments, for
specific actors based on these principles. Actors can be pri-
example, taking health functioning and health agency as
vate or public, but SHG relies on empirical evidence as to
central to human flourishing. An extensive discussion of
the most cost-effective route to achieving desired ends. Ac-
these points are beyond this article’s scope; an examina-
tors also have a duty to inculcate norms—for example, of
tion of health capabilities vis-`a-vis other capabilities (Ruger
health equity—in their own spheres of influence.
2009a) and routes to consensus amidst pluralism (Ruger
Medical providers (the medical profession and hos-
pitals, clinics, and other players) have duties to provide
PST thus offers some intellectual resources that support
high-quality goods and services to patients as efficiently as
an SHG view. Although PST cannot define what would con-
possible. Private and public insurers have a duty to insure
40 ajob
all citizens with a universal comprehensive benefits package
of health equity, serve as a focal point for responsibility; re-
of medically necessary and medically appropriate goods
sponsibility on the part of all parties for this joint endeavor
and services at the lowest possible costs. If these entities
is a basic premise for achieving the shared goal. This en-
cannot fulfill this duty more efficiently than the state, then
tails not just “group morality” but individual morality as
the state is to assume this duty. Empirical evidence from
well, preserving the methodological and normative impor-
comparative health systems suggests that the national gov-
tance of individuals and adding to it that of collectives as a
ernment is likely in the best position to insure the population
whole. Because SHG is designed positively to establish con-
with efficiency, equity, and control over costs (e.g., Hussey
ditions in which all have the ability to be healthy, it differs
and Anderson 2003; Reinhardt et al. 2004). Individuals and
from the traditional “motivation for responsibility” schol-
families have duties to promote their own health, fostered
arship, which takes causation, blameworthiness, and guilt
by self-interest, and we all (patients and other actors) owe
for harm as a point of departure. SHG is both an individual
each other a commitment to use our shared resources as
and group-based construct; both individuals and groups
wisely as possible. We also all share the duty to refrain from
can have health agency, intentions, and goals.
harming others and the system as a whole (e.g., throughfraudulent claims or making imprudent health choices).
Finally, the state shall allocate the duties of research
SOVEREIGNTY CONSTITUTIONAL
and education in a multistep process, first to governmental
COMMITMENTS
and nongovernmental institutions best positioned to make
A sixth basic feature of SHG is shared sovereignty. SHG
scientific decisions about such activity (e.g., the National
depends on individuals and groups coming together to de-
Institutes of Health [NIH], Institute of Medicine [IOM], Na-
velop structures and procedures to make decisions, govern
tional Science Foundation [NSF]), and then to entities such
collectively, and set standards for self-regulation and soci-
as universities and research institutes that fulfill this duty
etal regulation. While SHG brings in the overarching po-
by creating and disseminating knowledge.
litical economic philosophy put forth in Health and SocialJustice, SHG employs a constitution of sorts to delineate theends and means of health governance at the societal level. SHARED RESPONSIBILITY, COLLECTIVE
An SHG framework based on its own constitution will pro-
RESPONSIBILITY: A CAVEAT
vide a structure for different institutions as they relate to
Collective responsibility and shared responsibility have
each other (e.g., federal and state governments, civil soci-
multiple meanings, and a point of clarification on their ap-
ety, and individuals). As a superstructure, a “health consti-
plication in SHG is warranted. In SHG, individuals’ under-
tution” would delineate the respective actors (institutions,
standing of their roles leads them to take on the responsibil-
organizations, groups, individuals) in health governance
ity of doing their part successfully, pursuing specific goals
and specify their respective duties and powers, thus allo-
to achieve together the overarching social aim. My use of
cating specific responsibilities for creating a health society.
“shared responsibility” thus has quite specific functional
The health constitution would set the framework and proce-
and role-based foundations and entails particular commit-
dures informed by authoritative standards and principles.
ments, unlike broader, more existential notions of shared re-
Constitutional interpretation would then assess whether or
sponsibility. In essence, my use of “shared responsibility” is
not such duties have been fulfilled and whether actors are
a thin conception, linking explicit behavior and actions with
meeting their obligations to ensure conditions for all to be
values and attitudes to create conditions for all to be healthy.
healthy. To date the different actors in the health system
Existentialist responsibility has a more diffuse and general
(e.g., providers and physicians, federal and state govern-
structure; as one scholar notes, “Even when there is seem-
ment, insurers, clinics and hospitals, and individuals them-
ingly nothing that one can do to prevent an evil in the world,
selves) have not known what their respective duties and
one has a responsibility to distance oneself from that evil at
powers are. It would be difficult and unfair to attempt to
the very least by not condoning it” (May 1992, 3). Under a
hold them accountable for unspecified responsibilities. The
SHG framework, actors can and must do something—they
intent is to define effective institutional arrangements and
pursue their role-specific activities effectively.
divisions to bring about the conditions for a health society.
Shared responsibility under SHG is thus more narrow
This enterprise requires empirical research and evidence.
and delimited. What SHG shares with the social existential-
The health constitution is not a legal constitution, nor
ists, however, are two ideas: That both community mem-
does it overreach in governing every aspect of society. It
bership and shared attitudes create responsibilities for all
sets out meta-level rules for health, but it neither replaces
members (May 1992; Jaspers 2001; Smiley 2010), and that
nor competes with the legal “Constitution.” Rather, the two
individuals and groups are responsible for “joint actions
types of constitutionalism are complementary. The health
to which one contributes” (May 1992, 8). A change in atti-
constitution is constitutional in the sense of prescribing
tude is necessary so individuals and groups see themselves
institutional arrangements and procedures and in assign-
as sharing responsibility for creating the conditions for all
ing responsibilities and authorities to public and private
to be healthy, whether they do so by their own individual
actors. The principles set out in Health and Social Justice
actions or those actions they share with groups and insti-
imply a correlative obligation that falls on society as a
tutions. Ethical commitments to a shared goal, for example
whole. As the institution that represents society at large, the
ajob 41
government will need to spearhead the effort to map a plan
supply or demand side, in an individualized ad hoc capac-
for all entities. Through the health constitution it will have
ity. What is needed is the understanding that together, we
the ultimate responsibility for making sure this societal obli-
gation is met. The federal or national government has the
Still, “free rider” problems and failures to comply are
regulatory, legislative, taxation, and distributive authority
omnipresent in health and health care. SHG, drawing on
to oversee a just allocation of responsibility. The federal
PST, can help address and minimize these concerns. One
government has the authority and legitimacy to ensure the
approach is to demonstrate dependence or co-dependence
realization of important social goals. The health constitu-
among individuals as parties to a social group. This ap-
tion specifies the obligations of different actors. It is to be
proach appeals to the individualistic, rational side of per-
consistent with and undergirded by the public moral norms
sons and to social rationality, simultaneously, but it requires
monitoring, sanctioning, and a sense of co-dependence tomaintain stability (Hechter 1987). EXTERNAL AND INTERNAL MOTIVATION: FAILURE TO COMMIT, POSITIVE MOTIVATION, SOCIAL REACTIONS AND OBJECTIONS SANCTIONS, AND ENFORCEMENT
Reactions to the SHG model may come in a variety of forms,
The challenge is for people to commit, share resources, and
but I’d like to return just briefly to—and conclude with—a
agree to be held collectively responsible. Thus, individu-
discussion of what SHG is not in relation to existing social
als and groups can’t internalize just any social norm; it is
a set of public moral norms. Normative principles are dis-
First, SHG is not social solidarity. SHG is not nearly as
cussed and set forth, for example, in the health capability
communitarian and allows a more central role for individu-
paradigm, which spells out the reasons for equity in health
alism and self-regarding behavior. While examples of social
and explains why individuals and actors should see such
solidarity in health systems exist—for example, in universal
norms as socially rational. It may very well be, for example,
coverage in countries throughout the world—SHG is not
that many individuals, indeed most people in many soci-
just universal coverage, does not require a “common con-
eties, see health as an individual responsibility rather than
science” across life, and recognizes realistically that actors
a social obligation. In this case the heavy lifting is in peo-
conflict considerably (rather than cohere) in the division
ple committing, in persuading and convincing them of the
of labor (Durkheim 1933). While social solidarity meets the
necessity of the joint enterprise. This task in many cases is
SHG idea of shared resources, it is less focused on people
possible through positive motivation (see later description).
governing themselves to use resources parsimoniously.
There will also be a segment of the population that resists,
Social solidarity also doesn’t emphasize individual action
and, once institutions and procedures are put in place (as al-
and individual responsibility and doesn’t embrace, to the
ready described), in these cases an effective system of sanc-
extent in SHG, the opportunity to build a social system
tions, formal rules, and even laws and regulation may be
out of individual self- and other-regarding behavior. The
necessary to ensure that actors are fulfilling prescribed du-
Swiss and German systems, for instance, exhibit solidarity
ties. Thus, this fifth basic premise of SHG involves primarily
in the form of universal coverage (in Switzerland there is
positive, but in some cases negative, motivation to commit
universal coverage and one-third of individuals receive
to the joint enterprise. Even though numerous incentives
government subsidies to purchase health insurance)
and mechanisms of external motivation have been tried in
(Herzlinger and Parsa-Parsi 2004), yet the Swiss system is
virtually every health system worldwide, these efforts alone
second only to the United States in the proportion of gross
will not suffice to create the conditions approximating jus-
domestic product (GDP) spent on health care (OECD 2004),
and both Germany and Switzerland have had as much if
Drawing on what Gilbert calls “common knowledge,”
not more health care overutilization than the United States
the task of positive motivation is to generate common
(Weil 1994; Reinhardt 2004). Social solidarity is thus not
knowledge, self-understanding, and societal understand-
quite enough to contain costs and use shared resources
ing so that individuals are clear about both the empirical
wisely, nor are occupational or interest group affiliations
evidence and the values: Individual and population health
sufficient for solidarity in the health system; indeed, they
are inextricably linked, and improving our own health and
(e.g., medical profession and health insurance industry)
that of others requires the shared commitment of us all.
require greater governmental oversight. It further neglects
Health is a unique individual and social good, different
to address many of the other elements of SHG, particularly
from other types of private goods and requires a different
those focused on responsibility, constitutionalism in health,
magnitude of joint effort. Allowing self-interest maximiza-
and individual-level costs and benefits.
tion to run rampant throughout the health sector produces
Second, SHG is not socialism. Socialist health systems
suboptimal outcomes for everyone. Redefining individu-
are government funded and government run; the pub-
als’ self-understanding and institutionalizing this common
lic sector controls both funding and service delivery. The
knowledge underlie the SHG framework. As it stands, in
United Kingdom and Cuba are examples. By contrast, one
many health systems, even those fully nationalized, actors
of SHG’s distinguishing features is an emphasis on individ-
see themselves as interacting with the system, either on the
uals, private entities, and their actions, which are driven by
42 ajob
internalized norms promoting societal interests in addition
Arce M., D. G., and T. Sandler. 2003. Health-promoting alliances.
to their own. A public system may not necessarily be in-
European Journal of Political Economy 19: 355–375.
imical to SHG, though public funding and public service
Armstrong, D. 2005. Medical center is investigated for scan deals.
delivery cannot preclude active individual involvement in
Wall Street Journal July 28: B1.
Ashford, E., and T. Mulgan. 2009. Contractualism. The Stanford en-
Third, SHG is not just stewardship. In a way, social
cyclopedia of philosophy (winter 2009 edition), ed. E. N. Zalta. Avail-
solidarity and socialism can both be considered as mani-
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2009/entries/
festations of government stewardship: Government (with
various degrees of democratic backing) decides to imple-ment solidarity-based or socialist policies. As highly cen-
Aumann, R. J. 2008. Game theory. In The new Palgrave dictionary of
tralized and hierarchical health care systems show us, gov-
economics (2nd ed.), ed. S.N. Durlauf and L.E. Blume. Available
ernment directives and designs are not enough to ensure
at: http://www.dictionaryofeconomics.com/article?id=pde2008
good health outcomes, and laws are not always sufficient to
achieve health goals if popular norms oppose them. SHG
Baird, P., J. Downie, and J. Thompson. 2002. Clinical trials and
would seek to address pressure points where self-interest
maximization and/or social norms override government
Benda, D. 2003. Surgery charges high at RMC. Hospital ranked
laws and projects. In Japan, for example, despite legislation
fifth in U.S. for operating room markups. [Redding, CA] Record
to promote organ donation, rates of donation are low and
have been falling since the mid-1990s. One barrier is the re-luctance of family members to grant permission for organ
Bentham, J. 1961. An introduction to the principles of morals and
removal from the deceased (Ishida and Toma 2004). Govern-
legislation. Garden City, NY: Doubleday. [Originally published
ment action has not been able to overcome this normative
Binmore, K. 2005. Natural justice. New York: Oxford University
Fourth, SHG is not just enhanced autonomy, shared clin-
ical decision making, or enlightened self-interest. SHG is
Blakeley, G. 2010. Governing ourselves: Citizen participation and
more than consumer-directed medicine or the patient tak-
governance in Barcelona and Manchester. International Journal of
ing an active role in her own care with her physician or team
Urban and Regional Research 34(1): 130–145.
of providers. Decisions should account for both individual
Bombardier, C., L. Laine, A. Reicin, et al. 2000. Comparison of upper
and societal interests at every stage. Finally, following prin-
gastrointestinal toxicity of rofecobix and naproxen in patients with
ciples of “enlightened” self-interest or self-interest “rightly
rheumatoid arthritis. The VIGOR study group. New England Journal
understood” (de Tocqueville 1863), while interesting in the
of Medicine 343: 1520–1528.
abstract, has failed to curtail the emergence of the currentdysfunctional American health care system. Relying on en-
Bowles, S., and H. Gintis. 2008. Cooperation. In The new Palgrave
lightened self-interest as a guiding principle leaves us with-
dictionary of economics (2nd ed.), ed. S.N. Durlauf, and L.E. Blume.
out an overarching social objective toward which all have
Available at: http://www.dictionaryofeconomics.com/article?id=
respective roles and responsibilities in the joint enterprise
Broome, J. 1991. Weighing goods. Oxford: Blackwell.
Buchanan, A. 2009. Justice and health care. New York: Oxford Uni-versity Press. CONCLUSION
Cudd, A. 2008. Contractarianism. The Stanford encyclopedia of phi-
Achieving justice in health has eluded most nations. Eco-
losophy (fall 2008 edition), ed. E. N. Zalta. Available at: http://plato.
nomic rational choice theory based on Homo economicus, the
stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/contractarianism
dominant social theory of cooperation, has failed to ground
De Tocqueville, A. 1863. Democracy in America (3rd ed.) Cambridge,
an effective approach to health. Even when societies coop-
erate on a grand scale through national health policy andnational health systems, they do so in vastly different and
Durkheim, E. 1933. The division of labor in society. New York: Macmil-
often inadequate ways. It is a daunting challenge to allocate
responsibility, resources, and sovereignty to create condi-
Estlund, D. 2008. Democratic authority: A philosophical framework.
tions where all have the ability to be healthy. Some will ob-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
ject to SHG on the account that its conditions are too onerous
Finz, S. 2003. Guilty plea in medical fraud—12 patients die/Bay
and arguably implausible. Despite objections, shared health
area branch of Guidant fined $92 million over malfunctions. San
governance offers a promising new way forward. Francisco Chronicle June 13: A1.
Fischer, R. 2008. European governance still technocratic? Newmodes of governances for food safety regulation in the Euro-
REFERENCES
pean Union. European Integration Online Papers 12: 30 Decem-
Anderson, E. 2000. Beyond Homo economicus: New developments in
ber. Available at: http://eiop.or.at/eiop/index.php/eiop/article/
theories of social norms. Philosophy & Public Affairs 29(2): 170–200. ajob 43
Fraudguides.com. Medicaid fraud steals from everyone. Available at:
Mundy, A. 2004. Risk management. Harper’s Magazine September:
http://www.fraudguides.com/medical-medicaid-fraud.asp
Nagel, T. 1991. Equality and partiality. Oxford: Oxford University
Fudenberg, D., and E. Maskin. 1986. The folk theorem in repeated
games with discounting or with incomplete information. Economet-
Neshkova, M. I. 2010. How to share in governance effectively. PublicOrganization Review 10: 201–204.
Funtowicz, S. O., and J. R. Ravetz. 1993. Science for the post normal
Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development. 2004.
age. Futures 25(7): 739–755. OECD health data 2004. Paris: OECD.
Gauthier, D. 1986. Morals by agreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
O’Toole, K., J. Dennis, S. Kilpatrick, and J. Farmer. 2010. From
Gawande, A. 2009. The cost conundrum. The New Yorker June 1.
passive welfare to community governance: Youth NGOs in Aus-
Geyman, J. 2008. The corrosion of medicine. Monroe, ME: Common
tralia and Scotland. Children and Youth Services Review 32:
Gilbert, M. 1989. On social facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Palast, G. 2002. The best democracy money can buy. Sterling, VA: Pluto
Gilbert, M. 2003. The structure of the social atom: Joint commit-
Pugno, P. A., G. T. Schmittling, G. T. Fetter, and N. B. Kahn. 2005.
ment as the foundation of human social behavior. In Socializing
Results of the 2005 National Resident Matching Program: Family
metaphysics: The nature of social reality, ed. F. F. Schmitt, 39–64.
medicine. Family Medicine 37(8): 555–564.
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
Gutmann, A., and D. Thompson. 2002. Deliberative democracy be-
yond process. Journal of Political Philosophy 10(2): 153–174
Reinhardt, U. E. 2004. The Swiss health system: Regulated compe-
Harris, G., and A. Berenson. 2005. 10 Votes on panel backing pain
tition without managed care. Journal of the American Medical Associ-
pills had industry ties. New York Times February 25: A1.
Hartley, C. 2009. Justice for the disabled: A contractualist approach.
Reinhardt, U. E., P. S. Hussey, and G. F. Anderson. 2004. U.S. health
Journal of Social Philosophy 40(1): 17–36.
care spending in an international context. Health Affairs 23(3):10–25.
Hechter, M. 1987. Principles of group solidarity. Berkeley: Universityof California Press.
Rennie, D. M. 1997. Thyroid storm. Journal of the American MedicalAssociation 277: 1242.
Herzlinger, R. E., and R. Parsa-Parsi. 2004. Consumer-driven healthcare: Lessons from Switzerland. Journal of the American Medical As-
Roiseland, A. 2010. Local self-government or local co-governance?
sociation 292(10): 1213–1220.
Hussey, P., and G. F. Anderson. 2003. A comparison of single-
Rowland, D., and A. V. Telyukov. 1991. Soviet health care from two
and multi-payer health insurance systems and options for reform.
perspectives. Health Affairs (Fall): 71–86.
Ruger, J. P. 2004. Health and social justice. Lancet 364: 1075–1080.
Ishida, H., and H. Toma. 2004. Organ donation problems in Japan
Ruger, J. P. 2007. Health, health care, incompletely theorized agree-
and countermeasures. Saudi Journal of Kidney Diseases and Transplan-
ments. Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law 32(1): 51–87.
Ruger, J. P. 2009a. Health and social justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Jaspers, K. 2001. The question of German guilt, trans. E. B. Ashton.
Ruger, J. P. 2009b. Global health justice. Public Health Ethics 2(3):
Jochim, A. E., and P. J. May. 2010. Beyond subsystems: Policy
Ruger, J. P. 2010. Public engagement, deliberation, and shared health
regimes and governance. Policy Studies Journal 38(2): 303–327. governance. Presentation at American Society of Bioethics and Hu-
Lagnado, L. 2004. California hospitals open books, showing huge
manities Annual Conference, San Diego, California, October.
price differences. Wall Street Journal December 27.
Rummery, K. 2009. Healthy partnership, healthy citizens? An
Lemaire, J. 1984. An application of game theory: Cost allocation.
international review of partnerships in health and social care
ASTIN Bullein 14(1): 61–81.
and patient/user outcomes. Social Science & Medicine 69:
Levitt, S., and J. List. 2008. Homo economicus evolves. Science 319:
Scanlon, T. 1998. What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Lewis, M. 2006. Governance and corruption in public health care sys-tems. Working paper number 78. Washington, DC: Center for Global
Schmitt, F. F. 2003. Socializing metaphysics: An introduction. InSocializing metaphysics: The nature of social reality, ed. F. F. Schmitt,
May, L. 1992. Sharing responsibility. Chicago: University of Chicago
1–38. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Searle, J. 1990. Collective intentions and actions. In Intentions in
Meier, B. 2005. FDA says flaws in heart devices pose high risks. Communication, ed. P. Cohen, J. Morgan, and M. Pollack, 401–415.
44 ajob
Sidgwick, H. 1907. The methods of ethics (7th ed.) London:
Verbeek, B., and C. Morris. 2010. Game theory and ethics. TheStanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2010 edition), ed. E. N.
Smiley, M. 2010. Collective responsibility. The Stanford encyclopedia
Zalta. Available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/
of philosophy (summer 2010 edition), ed. E. N. Zalta. Available at:
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/collective-
Weil, T. P. 1994. Health reform in Germany. Health Progress
Starfield, B. 1994. Is primary care essential? Lancet 344: 1129–
Wendel, W. B. 2001. Nonlegal regulation of the legal profession:
Social norms in professional communities. Vanderbilt Law Review
Swidler, A. 2006. Syncretism and subversion in AIDS governance:
How locals cope with global demands. International Affairs 82(2):
Wikler, D. 2002. Personal and social responsibility for health. Ethics& International Affairs 16(2): 47–55.
Tuomela, R. 1984. A theory of social action. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Willman, D. 2000. How a new policy led to seven deadly drugs. Los
Ullmann-Margalit, E. 1977. The emergence of norms. Oxford: Oxford
Zabawa, B. J. 2003. Making the Health Insurance Flexibility and
Vallentyne, P. (ed.). 1991. Contractarianism and rational choice. Cam-
Accountability (HIFA) waiver work through collaborative gover-
nance. Annals of Health Law 12: 367–410. ajob 45
Q&A ABORTO PROVOCADO (agosto de 2011) Preguntas y respuestas acerca de la política holandesa sobre el aborto provocado. El folleto ‘Q&A Aborto Provocado’ responde a las preguntas que pueda tener el lector extranjero acerca de la legislación holandesa sobre el aborto. Esta publicación electrónica ha sido elaborada en colaboración con el Ministerio de Sanidad, Bienestar y Dep
KIRBY CHEMIST KIRBY CHEMIST KIRBY CHEMIST YOUR LOCAL PHARMACY YOUR LOCAL PHARMACY YOUR LOCAL PHARMACY There are five kinds of diabetes medicine are available in Two to four injections are necessary for type 1 diabetes. tablet form: Sulfonylureas, Biguanides, Glitinides, Thia-Insulin and/or tablet treatment can be more suitable for zolidinediones and Alpha Glucosidase inhi